ON THE DUTY TO CONSCIENTIOUSLY OBJECT

NONVIOLENCE, ACTIVISM, 26 Mar 2010

Camillo "Mac" Bica - Truthout

Moral values and norms are the means through which we define ourselves as persons, structure our world and render our relationship to it and to other human beings comprehensible. That is, moral values and norms provide the parameters of our being – what I term our “moral identity.” I submit that the moral principle of respect for persons is foundational to any reasonable, normative, ethical system. It is clear to me that if we do not respect and value persons, then respect for anything else we may hold “sacred,” whether it is property, country, the flag etc., loses all meaning. Morality requires, therefore, that we treat all persons as ends in themselves, not as a means to the ends of others, that all persons have intrinsic moral value, not instrumental value only. This principle is manifest as maintaining that all human beings have inalienable human rights, and correlative to these rights are the obligations of all moral agents to respect and not to violate them. It is clear to me as well that adhering to this rule, this principle, as foundational, will bring the greatest balance of good (benefit) over evil (detriment or harm) into the world for the greatest number of people. So, in a sense, then, this principle is not only Kantian, but Rule Utilitarian as well.

Unless one is an anarchist, since we choose to live in community with others, we must recognize the prima facie authority of the political structure within the state to make decisions about policy and actions that must be taken on behalf of the body politic. Further, when such decisions have been made utilizing established political processes, citizens are legally, perhaps even morally, obligated to concede at least a preliminary measure of authority to these decisions; even should they find them disagreeable. We must begin, therefore with a presumption in favor of decisions of state. The authority of the state, however, is not absolute and contingent upon the legality and morality of the particular policy being instituted or course of action being required.

Decisions of state may, in some situations, precipitate a crisis of conscience. Consider for example, a state’s decision to wage war. For the pacifist, inalienable human rights and the subsequent immunity afforded by such rights are absolute and cannot be overridden or forfeited. As war inevitably entails violence and killing, war is never a moral option. Consequently, the pacifist refuses participation, arguing that one’s moral obligation is absolute and, therefore, trumps/overrides any obligation one may have to the state. While never conceding its power to wage war, nations, including our own, have recognized the significance and accepted the importance of individualism, freedom of conscience and religious toleration. As such, governments have allowed pacifists a dispensation from having to serve in war by granting them general conscientious objector status.

For the nonpacifist, however, of whom I am one, moral rules and rights, since they can conflict, are not absolute, but prima facie. That is, under some conditions, rights and immunity can be forfeited, rendering the individual liable to be justifiably injured and/or killed in self-defense and war. For the nonpacifist, then, should certain very specific criteria be met (henceforth referred to as just war criteria), a war may be just and killing moral. Since, for the nonpacifist, some wars, wars that satisfy the just war criteria, may be morally justifiable, participation in such wars violates no moral principle and ought to provoke no objection of conscience.[1] Consequently, in the absence of a more stringent conflicting moral obligation, nonpacifists ought to abide by the morally and legally correct and duly arrived at decisions of government, even should they require service in war.

Unfortunately, not all wars that become the policy of governments are just and moral. Wars that fail to satisfy just war criteria, wars of aggression for example, violate the sanctity and inviolability of human life and the tenets of international law, treaties, United States military law and the principles of morality. Consequently, such wars are both illegal and immoral.

The order to participate in an unjust war and, hence, to kill nonliable human beings (innocents) – to commit murder – is an illegal and immoral order. Consequently, the authority of government to require participation in such a war is forfeit, and citizens, whether they are civilians or members of the military, have no obligation to obey such an order, despite the war being a duly enacted decision of government. The Nuremberg Principles make this obligation clear: “[T]he very essence of the [Nuremberg] Charter is that individuals have intentional duties which transcend the national obligations of obedience imposed by the individual state.”

In fact, according to morality and law there is an obligation NOT to participate, a duty to refuse, an obligation of selective conscientious objection. In addition, at the Tokyo War Crimes Tribunal, it was further declared that there is a legal obligation to work toward ending unjust wars.

Anyone with knowledge of illegal activity and an opportunity to do something about it is a potential criminal under international law unless the person takes affirmative measures to prevent commission of the crimes.

Selective conscientious objection, then, is the claim by nonpacifists first, that a particular war fails to satisfy the just war criteria; second, that it is illegal and immoral; and third, that all moral agents are obligated not to abide by the decisions of government and to refuse to participate in or to support the prosecution of this particular war. Consequently, in an unjust war, since law and morality are in agreement, there is no conflict between a citizen’s moral and legal obligation. Paradoxically, despite the clarity of international, domestic and moral law regarding illegal and immoral war, few governments, including our own, recognize selective conscious objection.

Where the general conscientious objector, the pacifist, the selective conscientious objector and the just war theorist differ is that with the former only sincerity of belief is relevant. But with the latter, in addition to sincerity of belief, correctness of conscience is not only relevant, but required. That is, conscience is not infallible. There are those – members of the Westboro Baptist Church come to mind – who believe sincerely that God hates homosexuals as well as all members of the military, Catholics, Jews etc. I will grant them the benefit of the doubt that they are sincere in their beliefs and acting in accordance with their conscience, outrageous and perverted though their behavior may be. Consequently, since there is a prima facie obligation to abide by just and moral policy determined through accepted means of governance, nonpacifists citizens must either participate in war or bear the burden of proof to demonstrate correctness of conscience, that is, establish how/why the war in question is illegal and immoral.

Transparency in government, that is, providing the information necessary to create an informed citizenry, is a requirement in a democracy if government by and for the people is to work successfully. Political leaders, then, must, before waging war, offer a coherent, rational and valid argument that just war criteria have been satisfied, that is, despite the awfulness of war, killing and destruction is a necessary, just and moral recourse in this particular situation.

In bringing attention to moral and legal concerns that should be of vital interest to all moral agents, especially to those charged with the responsibilities of governing, the selective conscientious objector is a great asset to the state. That is, the selective conscientious objector is telling us that, in his view, and for these reasons, a particular war has failed to satisfy just war criteria and, hence, is in violation of international, military and moral law. Such objections may be correct or incorrect, but either way, they ought to be taken seriously by the government as they provide an important opportunity to review and re-evaluate the decision to wage war.

However the Supreme Court chooses to interpret, and political and military leaders choose to implement conscientious objection, the legal precedent and moral obligation is clear. Consequently, we do not need further legislation recognizing a right to selective conscientious objection because it is already not only recognized, but required both by law and morality. What is necessary, however, is that governments and the military begin taking these objections seriously. That is, our political and military leaders should welcome the observations and criticisms of the selective conscientious objector as a means either to reaffirm their decision to wage war, or to correct and make retribution for their transgressions or tragic mistakes in policy. A nation that persists in waging unjust, immoral war is a pariah in the international community, a rogue nation, and its leaders, war criminals.

NOTE

[1] Given the moral gravity of one’s actions in war, however, it may well be the case that warriors may still suffer “moral injury.” See my “The Moral Casualties of War: Understanding the Experience,” International Journal of Applied Philosophy, v.13:1, Spring 1999, p 81.

__________________________

Camillo “Mac” Bica, Ph.D., is a professor of philosophy at the School of Visual Arts in New York City. He is a former Marine Corps Officer, Vietnam Veteran, and the Coordinator of the Long Island Chapter of Veterans for Peace.


GO TO ORIGINAL – TRUTHOUT.ORG

Share this article:


DISCLAIMER: The statements, views and opinions expressed in pieces republished here are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of TMS. In accordance with title 17 U.S.C. section 107, this material is distributed without profit to those who have expressed a prior interest in receiving the included information for research and educational purposes. TMS has no affiliation whatsoever with the originator of this article nor is TMS endorsed or sponsored by the originator. “GO TO ORIGINAL” links are provided as a convenience to our readers and allow for verification of authenticity. However, as originating pages are often updated by their originating host sites, the versions posted may not match the versions our readers view when clicking the “GO TO ORIGINAL” links. This site contains copyrighted material the use of which has not always been specifically authorized by the copyright owner. We are making such material available in our efforts to advance understanding of environmental, political, human rights, economic, democracy, scientific, and social justice issues, etc. We believe this constitutes a ‘fair use’ of any such copyrighted material as provided for in section 107 of the US Copyright Law. In accordance with Title 17 U.S.C. Section 107, the material on this site is distributed without profit to those who have expressed a prior interest in receiving the included information for research and educational purposes. For more information go to: http://www.law.cornell.edu/uscode/17/107.shtml. If you wish to use copyrighted material from this site for purposes of your own that go beyond ‘fair use’, you must obtain permission from the copyright owner.

Comments are closed.